Traditional vision science is very excited about illusions. These are cases when perception seems to break down; there is a mismatch between what is out there and what we experience, and traditional approaches consider these breakdowns as clues to how vision has to work, given what it is working with.
Ecological psychologists don’t like illusions. Typically, they occur when information is either made ambiguous or faked, and in general we think these are the wrong situations to study perception in. We sometimes engage with the literature on these effects, but usually to show how the trick is the result of not thinking ecologically.
Rogers (2022) has taken this basic analysis but gone one interesting step further. He’s argued that the notion of ‘visual illusion’ is simply not a clear category; it’s not a useful way to describe any of the effects people study. He argues that there simply is no sufficient definition of what an illusion is that works, and that what we call illusions are just either tricks (as above) or inevitable consequences of how the visual system works.
I am broadly on board with this additional step, and it’s made me think hard about what illusions are and how best to respond when people use them against direct perception.
Rogers first argues that no-one actually has a good account of what an illusion even is. The standard definition is Gregory’s: an illusion occurs when there is a mismatch between what is really out there, and what we experience. An illusion is an error. (Rogers also spends some time looking at a modern analysis by Todorovic (2020) which has, according to Rogers, basically the same idea at the core and therefore the same limitations.)
The problem here is that there are many ways to describe ‘what is really out there’, and a long-standing ecological objection to illusions is that the mismatch is an artefact of the researcher having the wrong description. Gibson spent the first 4 chapters of the 1979 book describing an ecological reality for a reason! So the mismatch is often just an analysis error, not a perceptual one. A corollary to this is that illusion results are often telling us about our understanding of the relevant physics, and not about perception.
Rogers then describes three ways to classify candidate illusion effects that he suggests covers the space without ever needing the notion of error. I think an interesting step going forward will be to try and apply these three categories to all and any illusion discussions from here on out, to see if it holds up.
The first are effects that would never fit any definition of illusion. He discusses the Ames Room, where a non-rectangular room is made to appear as if it were rectangular when viewed from a particular place. Rogers identifies that it’s simply unfair to consider this an error by the visual system, because it is being meticulously fooled – it is being presented with what Rogers calls a facsimile, something designed to look a certain way. It’s not an error for the visual system to perceive a good facsimile as the other thing; how could it possibly do anything else? If it’s not an error, then it cannot sensibly be called an illusion. (I blogged Runeson's excellent analysis of the Ames Room, which Rogers is endorsing here).
The second are effects due to how the system works. His first simple example is thresholds. If there ‘really is’ a dim light present but the visual system doesn’t register it because it is below threshold, it’s not an error; it’s simply a result of the way the system works. In the same way, (my example) it’s not an error when a microphone fails to respond to light but does to sound, because that’s how microphones work. Colour metamers is another example for Rogers; we don’t consider these errors but simply what happens when a trichromatic system is operating normally. These are simply how the visual system measures the world, and calling these effects errors/illusions is just to not understand this fact.
The third are effects of using impoverished situations. Rogers point is simply that it has to be true that the system will fail in some way when you remove information the system requires to work properly. Calling this an error is unfair. Rogers doesn't quite spell this out clearly, but I think this is a combination of the above two situations: the impoverished setting can't actually be seen any other way, because of how the perceptual system works. There is an additional concern here, though, that Rogers focuses on; not only is it unfair to consider these errors/illusions, they aren't good experiments. The logic of these studies is usually that systematically removing potential sources of information (typically framed as cues) tests whether those were, in fact, important. But this subtractive approach to perception assumes that the system is linear: that the full system and the system missing one cue only differ in that one cue. But this isn't the case; Rogers reviews some examples here, but my favorite is always Mon-Williams & Bingham (2008). They tested distance perception under full cue and restricted cue conditions, and basically showed that a) people will use the non-specifying height-in-the-visual-field when that's all there is, but that b) they show no signs of using it when better information is present. Studying perception in a restricted-cue task tells you how perception works in that task, but not how it works in the typical full-cue setting.