"Odd as it may sound today, democracy was a catastrophe for Jews, who thrived in liberal autocracies." (p. 19)
"Phenomenology, coming first from Husserl and then from his student Heidegger, offered the appealing ideal that the self was something deeper than the Fruedian psychological self. It proposed a notion of authenticity in an inauthentic world." (p. 37)
"Anglicanism is not Protestantism. The Church of England was and is a weird animal: at its most conservative, it is far more ornate and tradition-bound than its Episcopalian brethren in the U.S. In essence, High Anglicanism was Catholicism without the Pope. On the other hand, at its low end, the Anglican Church can resemble Scandinavian Protestantism: under-adorned, its authority vested in a single, often rather gaunt and morally and sartorially restrained pastor....What unites this weird religion is its long-established identification with power. From that little church in a Norfolk village through the High Anglican cathedrals of Liverpool or York, this is the "Church of England." Historically, the link between church and state in England has been usually intimate, the rule elite overwhelmingly drawn from Anglican families and the church itself umbilically attached to the political establishment....The establishment identity associated with Anglicanism is thus of far greater significance than its rather nebulous theological markers. This was above all an English church; its Christianity could at times appear almost secondary." (p. 73)
"G.E. Moore, the Cambridge philosopher, it seems fair to say, is what Nietzsche would have looked like had he been born in England." (p. 81)
"Following the Bolshevik Revolution of 1917, there was a sharp and enduring schism between those who could not digest the human consequences of their own [Marxist] theories, and those for whom these same consequences were nasty in just the way they had thought they would be, and all the more convincing for that reason: it's really hard; we've really got to make difficult choices; we have no choice but to do bad things; this is a revolution; if we are in the omelette-making business, this is not the moment to coddle the eggs. In other words, this is a break with the past and with our enemies, justified and explained by an all-embracing logic of human transformation. Marxists for whom all of this suggested mere repression were (not altogether unreasonably) accused of failing the grasp the implications of their own doctrine and condemned to the dustbin of History." (p. 94)
"For the fist time I came to appreciate that Israel was not a social-democratic paradise of peace-loving, farm-dwelling Jews who just happened to be Israelis but were otherwise just like me....The junior officers I met were drawn from the cities and towns rather than the kibbutzim, and thanks to them I came to appreciate something that should have been obvious to me long before: that the dream of rural socialism was just that." (p. 117)
"In the Christian version of Jewish history, Jews--Christ-like--can only truly win when (or rather, after) they lost. If they appear victorious, to be gaining their ends (at someone else's expense) there is a problem. But this otherwise elegant European appropriation of someone else's history for other purposes raises complications. The first of these...is that Israel is there." (p. 122)
"A Zionist, we used to say, is a Jew who pays another Jew to live in Israel. American is full of Zionists." (p. 125)
"As for cultural studies, I found them depressingly superficial: driven by the need to separate social data and experience from any economic roots or influences, the better to distinguish their claims from the discredited Marxism on which they otherwise drew shamelessly....What happens, after all, when the proletariat ceases to function as an engine of history? At the hands of practitioners of cultural and social studies in the 1970s the machine could still be made to work: you merely replaced "workers" with "women"; or students, or peasants, or blacks, or--eventually--gays, or indeed whichever group had sound reason to be dissatisfied with the present disposition of power and authority....All this struck me as jejune and callow." (p. 155)
"The prospects of fascism...depend upon a country being trapped in some combination of mass society and fragile, fragmented political institutions. As of today, I can think of nowhere in the West where these conditions obtain in a sufficiently acute form." (p. 166)
"Those who did not believe Orwell in 1939 would be forced to backtrack in later years: from 1945 through the mid-fifties, a crucial element in all the Soviet Bloc trials of those years...would be the actions of the accused during the Spanish Civil War....In that sense, communist strategy in Spain turns out to have been a dry run for the seizure of power in Eastern Europe after 1945. Obviously, this was very hard to appreciate at the time. Moscow, after all, was the only significant and effective backer of the Spanish republic. The Soviet Union was increasingly regarded as the only remaining bulwark against the rise of fascism in Central and Eastern Europe--and therefore Spain too. Everyone else, including Britain, was more than happy to compromise, so long as they were not affected themselves." (p. 190)
"The real Cold War at the intellectual and cultural level, and also at the political level in many countries, was not fought between the Left and the right but within the Left. The real political fault line fell between communists and fellow traveling sympathizers, on the one side, and social democrats, on the other wise....Culturally, the fault line drawn by the inherited cultural politics of the 1930s. Once you understand this, you can see who the Cold War liberals were. They were people like Sidney Hook....an aggressively socialist critic of communism." (p. 226)
"The crucial asset of Western liberalism was not its intellectual appeal but its institutional structures." (p. 230)
"By the last decade of the twentieth century, opposition in Eastern Europe was frequently and plausibly presented not just as a revolution within politics but also against them. The transformation gave the smarter neo-liberals their opening: a way to ditch the dissidents while stealing their clothes. If politics as usual has been replaced by "anti-politics," then we live in a post-political world. And in a post-political world, shorn of ethical meaning or historical narrative, what remains? Certainly not society. All that is left, as Margaret Thatcher famously insisted, are "families and individuals." And their self-interest, economically defined." (p. 248)
"From an academic point of view, New York resembles the continental European model rather than the Anglo-American template. The most important conversations in town are not those conducted among academics behind college walls, but the broader intellectual and cultural debate exchanged across the city and taking in journalists, independent writers, artists and visitors as well as the local professoriate. Thus, at least in principle, universities are culturally and intellectual integrated into the wider conversation. In this sense at least, by staying in New York I could also remain European." (p. 255)
"Many historians today do indeed regard history as an exercise in applied political polemic. The point is to reveal something about th past that conventional narratives have camouflaged: to correct some misreading of the past, usually in order to engage as parti pris in the present. When this is undertaken with crass shamelessness, I find it depressing. It so obviously betrays the purpose of history, which is to understand the past." (p. 259)
"You cannot teach children American history by saying: it is widely believed that the Civil War was about the abolition of slavery, but ha!--I can assure you that is was really about something else altogether. For the poor little things in the front row are turning to one another and asking: 'What a minute, what's she talking about? What is the Civil War? When did it happen? Who won?'" (p. 266)
"I think that in one form or another, this is challenge facing any serious intellectual today: how to be a consistent universalist. It is not just a simple matter of saying: I believe in rights, freedoms or this or that norm. Because if you believe in people's freedom to choose, but you also believe you know better than others what is good for them, then you face a potential contradiction. How can one as a consistent universalist impose one culture or one set of preferences on another--but how can one decline to do so if one takes one's own values seriously? And even if we allow that this problem could be resolved, how can we be sure that we have avoided other contradictions in a necessarily complex political world/" (p. 290)
"It's a very odd experience for an English person, and I think even more so for a continental European, to come to America and discover the deeply felt national identification of even its most liberal and cosmopolitan citizens--something that is on the whole not the case in Europe. It was once the case that the forms of state-and-nation identification were part of the required civic life....but it's not that they were deeply embedded in what it meant to be a certain national, it's just that they were part of the tradition: like the tartan in Scotland....The American traditions are now so profoundly embedded that it's very hard to distinguish them from what it means to be American: that is why perfectly reasonable American citizens can get genuinely angry when someone fails to salute the flag or sing the anthem. Such sentiments are unknown in contemporary Europe." (p. 302)
"The tendency of mass democracy to produce mediocre politicians is what worries me." (p. 309)
"Today it takes a very considerable degree of ethical self-confidence to say, as people used to as recently as the Watergate era, that such-and-such a person is a bad politician because he lies. Not because he lies as a spokesman for the arms lobby, or the gun lobby, or whatever it might be--but just because he lies....The historical background to this disturbing loss of moral confidence seems to me in large measure the collapse of the old Left, with all its faults, and the attendant ascendency of the soft cultural Left. Thus American liberals feel vaguely uncertain about what exactly the ground is that they stand on when they say that they disapprove of something. We're easier with the problem of good and evil if it is unambiguously located in another time (or place); we're more comfortable saying we don't like witch dunking, or we don't like the Gestapo. But we are not always clear how we should state our opposition to, e.g., female clitorectomies in East Africa--for fear of giving cultural offense. And that hands huge hostages to those (normally but not always on the right) who, in a much cruder way, think they know exactly what's right and wrong, false and real, and so one. And who are willing to say so in a self-assertive, confident way. The problem of ethical insecurity has kneecapped two generations of liberals." (p. 317)
"At what point is it legitimate for a government to simply say that a certain commodity or service is better provided publicly? When is it right to create a natural public monopoly? But since 1980 or so, the question has been posed differently: why should they be any public monopolies? Why should not everything be open to profit? It is that visceral suspicion of any sort of public monopoly in anything that could in principle be rendered private that we live with, or have lived with, for the last twenty-five years. And I don't, by the way, think that it's going to change now because of the overhyped crisis in capitalism that we're passing through now. I think that what we're going to see more is the acceptability if government as regulator--but government as monopolizer of certain kinds of good and services we will not see." (p. 363)
"Like debt, gambling was long frowned upon and mostly banned. It was widely and correctly assumed that gambling led to criminality and was thus a social pathology to be avoided. But of course it was also regarded in a long-standing Christian tradition as wrong in itself: money should not beget money. We would benefit from revisiting that perspective." (p. 367)
"The twentieth century was not necessarily as we have been taught to see it. It was not, or not only, the great battle between democracy and fascism, or communism versus fascism, or left versus right, or freedom versus totalitarianism. My own sense is that for much of the century we were engaged in implicit or explicit debates over the rise of the state. What sort of state did free people want? What were they willing to pay for it and what purposes did they wish it to serve? In the perspective, the great victors of the twentieth century were the nineteenth century liberals whose successors created the welfare state in all its protean forms. They achieved something which, as late as the 1930s, seemed almost inconceivable: they forged strong, high-taxing and actively interventionist democratic and constitutional states which could encompass complex mass societies without resorting to violence or repression. We would be foolish to abandon this heritage carelessly." (p. 386)
Tony Judt, requiescat in pace.